Beauty of mathematical incompleteness
Kurt Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem states the following:
“Any consistent formal system F within which a certain amount of elementary arithmetic can be carried out is incomplete; i.e. there are statements of the language of F which can neither be proved nor disproved in F.” (Raatikainen 2020)
This statement is dense, but it’s worth pondering because its philosophical weight is enormous: it means that no sufficiently strong formal system can capture all mathematical truths.
Traditionally, this has been read as a lament of the great field of mathematics: no matter how well chosen, powerful, or useful our axioms appear, there will always be truth they cannot capture.
Philosophy
The Philosophy of Mathematics is a field unto itself; however, the competing ideas of Platonists and Structuralists are the relevant camps to my points here. In essence, platonists see mathematics as a realm of eternal truths waiting to be discovered; structuralists see it as the exploration of formal systems and their consequences
This is typically interpreted, under a Platonic view of mathematics, to imply some sort of flaw or fundamental limitation of mathematics, since it concludes that any given system must have unprovable results. Therfore, incompleteness proves a disconnect between us and a realm of objective mathematical truth.
However, I believe it is much more enlightening to view this from a structuralist’s perspective.
Rather than interpreting Gödel’s findings as a limitation of mathematics, I believe it demonstrates that mathematics is actually inexhaustable. The guaranteed boundary of an formal system acts as a branch point between an infinite collection of explorable mathematical structures. Mathematics is not broken; it is in fact infinitely deep- so much so that its results cannot possibly be contained in any given formal system.
Perhaps unintuitively, if mathematics were “complete”, it would actually be stifling. We would be able to contain the whole of mathematics- but it would also mean that mathematics was small enough to be contained.
In this way, each “boundary” is not a wall but a fork in the road, leading to new mathematical landscapes; and each of these new landscapes are guaranteed to have forks of their own. Incompleteness guarantees that mathematics is not a closed book, but an endlessly branching tree.
Motivating Example
Much of the structural beauty that I want to convey is abstract: the guarantee of axiomatic branches, infinite depth of nested structures, etc; however, I think the impact can be best demonstrated with a more practical example.
Geometry as a systematic field of study can be traced to Euclid and his famous work Elements where he establishes the following postulates for geometry:
- A straight line can be drawn joining any two points.
- A finite straight line can be extended indefinitely in a straight line.
- A circle can be drawn with any center and radius.
- All right angles are equal.
(More contemporary mathematicians, such as Hilbert and Birkhoff, provided their own rigorous axioms for geometry; however, they all describe the same system precisely, so it is sufficient to use Euclid’s casual approach.)
There is one more postulate that Euclid provided which is referred to as the Parallel Postulate:
- If a line segment intersects two straight lines forming two interior angles on the same side that are less than two right angles, then the two lines, if extended indefinitely, meet on that side on which the angles sum to less than two right angles.
The inclusion of this postulate is the distinctive axiom of Euclidean geometry.
Later mathematicians, in an attempt to reduce geometry to as few axioms as possible, considered if the Parallel Postulate could be proven from the previous four postulates (in which case, it would be redundant), since parallelism seems to be an obvious property of geometry. However, they found that if you describe geometry without the Parallel Posulate, you could form valid, albeit different geometric systems.
Additionally, these non-Euclidean geometries, like much of mathematics, eventually proved to be vital to the sciences. Notably, non-Euclidean geometries are essential for Einstein’s general theory of relativity.
In effect, geometry as defined by the first four axioms could not prove whether the Parallel Postulate held, and, in fact, different and rich mathematical structures are formed depending on its inclusion.
Suppose the Parallel Postulate had been provable from Euclid’s other axioms; then non-Euclidean geometries- and with them, much of modern physics- would never have emerged. The “failure” to prove the Parallel Posulate was actually the doorway to richer structures.
The beauty of the First Incompleteness Theorem is that it guarantees the existence of infinite branching mathematical systems such as this. Gödel assures us that such discoveries are not historical accidents, but structural necessities.
Conclusion
If Platonism views incompleteness as a tragic loss, and structuralism views it as infinite branching, perhaps Gödel nudges us beyond this dichotomy altogether. Maybe the “reality” about mathematics is neither a fixed Platonic realm nor a mere game of formal systems, but the generative process itself—the unfolding of structures and the creation of new worlds from undecidable questions.
Because of incompleteness, mathematics can never run out of new directions to explore; there will always be new geometries, new logics, new structures. In this way, incompleteness is an unexpected, undeserved gift- not a curse.